Wednesday, October 3, 2012

Gulliver's Travels

The following are supplementary material designed to augment our enjoyment of Swift's Gulliver's Travels, which engages directly in philosophical, political, cultural, and nationalistic questions of early eighteenth century.

Personalities

Sir Robert Walpole (one of the targets of Swift's satire) and a major political figure of the period



Sir Robert Walpole by Arthur Pond Sir Robert Walpole by Arthur Pond  © Walpole was a British Whig statesman, considered to the first holder of the office of prime minister, who dominated politics in the reigns of George I and George II.
Robert Walpole was born on 26 August 1676 in Houghton, Norfolk into a wealthy landowning family. He was educated at Cambridge University and in 1701 became member of parliament for Castle Rising in Norfolk, where his father had previously been MP. He rose rapidly, becoming a member of the Admiralty Board, secretary of war and, in 1709, treasurer of the navy. His rise was temporarily halted by the Tories, who came into power in 1710. In 1712, they accused him of corruption and he was briefly imprisoned.
In 1714, George I came to the throne. George distrusted the Tories, whom he believed opposed his right to the throne, and as a result the Whigs were in the ascendant again. In 1715, Walpole became first lord of the treasury and chancellor of the exchequer. He resigned in 1717 after disagreements within his party but in 1720 was made paymaster general. He avoided the scandal that surrounded the collapse of the South Sea Company and was subsequently appointed first lord of the treasury and chancellor of the exchequer again. In this position he effectively became prime minister, although the term was not used at the time. He remained in this position of dominance until 1742.
Walpole consolidated Whig power through a system of royal patronage. He pursued a policy of peace abroad, low taxation and reducing the national debt and he knew the importance of keeping parliament on his side. He was also accused of bribery and corruption in his efforts to retain power. After George I's death in 1727, Walpole was briefly superseded by George II's favourite, Spencer Compton, but succeeded in returning himself to favour, partly through the support of the new queen, Caroline. In 1735, George II made Walpole a gift of 10 Downing Street, now the permanent London residence of the British prime minister.
Opposition eventually began to develop within Walpole's own party, and a trade dispute with Spain was used by his critics to force him to declare war in 1739, known as the War of Jenkins' Ear. A poor general election result in 1741 made his position more unstable. A number of Whig politicians opposed Walpole's conduct of the war and he resigned in February 1742. He was created earl of Orford in the same year and continued to maintain influence over George II. Walpole died on 18 March 1745.
http://www.bbc.co.uk/history/historic_figures/walpole_robert.shtml

Henry St. John Bolingbroke (1678—1751)

bolingbroke

Henry St. John Bolingbroke was born in Battersea in 1678. He was educated at Eton and Oxford, after which he traveled about two years on the continent. In 1700, shortly after his return, he married the daughter of Sir Henry Winchcomb, from whom he soon separated. Up to this period, he was chiefly known for his extreme dissipation but, after entering parliament in 1701, he devoted himself to politics, joined the Tory party, and soon made himself prominent as an orator. In 1704 he was made secretary of war and retained this office until 1708 when the Whigs came into power, after which he retired from politics and applied himself to study. After resignation, Bolingbroke retained great influence as the queen’s favorite counselor. On the fall of the Whig party in 1710, he was made secretary of state for foreign affairs. In 1712, he was called to the house of lords by the title of Viscount Bolingbroke and in 1713, against the wishes of nearly the entire nation, concluded the peace of Utrecht. Having previously quarreled with his old friend Harley, now the Earl of Oxford and his most powerful rival, he contrived his dismissal in July 1714. Bolingbroke immediately proceeded to form a strong Jacobite ministry in accordance with the well-known inclinations of his royal mistress, whose death a few days after threw into disorder his dangerous and unprincipled schemes. The accession of George I was a deathblow to Bolingbroke’s political prospects, on August 28 he was deposed from office, in March 1715 he fled to France and, in August 1715 he was attainted. For some time he held the office of secretary of state to the Pretender, but his restless and ambitious spirit yearned for the ‘large excitement’ of English politics. Bolingbroke’s efforts to obtain a pardon were not successful and he retired to a small estate which he had purchased near Orleans. In 1718 his first wife died and, in 1720, he married the rich widow of the Marquis de Vilette.
A prudent use of this lady’s wealth enabled him to return to England in September 1724. His property was restored to him, but he was never permitted to take his seat in parliament. He therefore removed himself to his villa at Dawley, near Uxbridge, where he occasionally enjoyed the society of Swift, Pope, and others of his old friends with whom he had corresponded in his exile. It was at Dawley where Bolingbroke diversified his moral and metaphysical studies by his attacks on the ministry in his periodical the Craftsman, in which the letters forming his Dissertation on Parties first appeared. In 1735, finding his political hopes clouded forever, he went back to France and continued to live there until 1742. During his second residence abroad, he wrote his Letters on the Study of History in which he violently attacked the Christian religion. He died on October 1, 1751, after a long illness. His talents were brilliant and versatile; his style of writing was polished and eloquent; but his fatal lack of sincerity and honest purpose, and the low and unscrupulous ambition which made him scramble for power with a selfish indifference to national security, hindered him from looking wisely and deeply into any question. His philosophical theories are not profound, nor his conclusions solid, while his criticism of passing history is worthless.

Bolingbroke’s philosophical writings were mostly unprinted until after his death, when David Mallet published a five-volume collection of Bolingbroke’s works. The philosophical portions of this collection display his dependence on Locke, who Bolingbroke acknowledged as his “master.” Using Locke’s ideas and his own, Bolingbroke attempts to explain how one attains knowledge and what its limits are, as well as asserting his own beliefs about God and religion. In doing so, he makes virulent attacks on previous philosophers such as Plato, Malebranche, and Berkley.
Following Locke, Bolingbroke distinguishes between ideas of sensation and ideas of reflection. Borrowing further from Locke, he calls these “simple ideas” and says they are the materials out of which complex ideas are made. He goes on to say that although one may not understand the process by which objects produce sensory perceptions, one can know they do so. Likewise, one may not know how the will causes action, such as the movement of an arm, but this does not hinder one from knowing it is the will which causes it. He presents these beliefs as clear and obvious and in no need of being questioned. Bolingbroke gives less power, than does Locke, to the mind concerning its ability to combine ideas within itself, putting this power in nature instead. Bolingbroke also maintains that nature (the observable world) serves as a reliable guide, and error comes when one uses one’s faculties out of accordance with nature.
Bolingbroke is known for being a Deist. He asserts there is a God, and proving this by reason is possible. However, this God is not at all like humans, and Bolingbroke speaks of anthropomorphism with contempt. Instead, he says God is so dissimilar to human beings, the distance between them is unimaginable and no comparison between the two is possible. Bolingbroke uses the cosmological argument to demonstrate there is a God, but goes on to assert that this God is omnipotent and omniscient and always does what is best. (Bolingbroke even claims this is the best of all possible worlds.) In order to defend his view of God’s transcendence, Bolingbroke says that while one can be certain God knows everything, one can never comprehend the way in which He knows things, and goes as far as to say God’s manner of knowing cannot be understood by human beings. God’s morality is equally beyond human understanding. Our moral values are based solely on our existence as social beings who cannot live lives of isolation or follow a path of pure selfishness. These morals can be discovered by reason. While they arise out of the nature of things created by God, they are in no way indicative of a divine sense of morality. God created the world, and the nature of the world determines morality. However, this nature does not reflect the character or nature of God.
Bolingbroke states Christianity was originally a “complete” and “very plain system of religion,” was actually no more than the “natural religion,” and Jesus did not teach anything more than could be discovered by reason. Bolingbroke expresses regret that Christian teachings did not remain at their initial, simple level, and wishes they had never been corrupted by such systems as Platonism, which he regards as the product of mere imagination. His understanding of religion furthermore denies the validity of prayer by insisting one could not come into contact with one’s deity, denigrates the importance of the crucifixion in Christianity, and suggests one cannot know whether or not there is a soul which survives the death of the body.
http://www.iep.utm.edu/bolingbr/

Robert Harley, Earl of Oxford

Robert Harley, Earl of Oxford, was a senior political figure in the reign of Queen Anne. Harley became her senior minister and acted as Secretary of State (1704 to 1708) and Lord Treasurer (1711 to 1714). The death of Anne and the succession of the Hanoverian George I effectively ended Harley's political career.

Robert Harley was born on December 5th 1661, the son of the moderately Puritan Sir Edward Harley who had been a supporter of Parliament during the English Civil War. Harley had a Puritan upbringing at the Haymarket Dissenting Academy and in 1682 attended the Middle Temple. In 1688, he accompanied his father in his capture of Worcester for William of Orange – the future William III.

When William III was king, Harley served as a backbench MP with the Country Whigs. These were men who had a great deal of sympathy for the rural way of life as opposed to the urban way of living. Harley, a country squire, would have fitted in naturally with this group. Harley was a great believer in honest and open government and he developed a hatred of political corruption - something that he associated with those in the finance and commercial houses of the City of London. Harley himself became a very skilful political manager and while he was associated with the Country Whigs, he was not a party person. Harley became an expert on constitutional history and his reputation was such that aged just 29 he was appointed to the Public Accounts Institution – the accepted institution of governmental opposition. BY 1695, Harley was acknowledged as its leader.

He, along with others, formed the New Country Party that historians view as the embryonic Tory Party of Queen Anne’s reign. Made up of Tories and Whigs, its members internally bickered on a variety of issues but managed by Harley, it became a major player in English politics. In February 701, Harley was appointed Speaker of the House by the king – a royal recognition of his managerial ability and the political status he now held.

Under Queen Anne, Harley became one of the Triumvirate – three men who dominated politics at that time. Marlborough was the military heart of the three; Sidney Godolphin was Lord Treasurer and used his political skill to raise the funding for the Spanish War of Succession while Harley was the effective political manager, first as Speaker and then as Secretary of State.

One of the ways that Harley used to manage Parliament was to create a large network of political informers that left him as “the best informed politician of his day.” (E N Williams)

Domestically, the most important issue that Harley was associated with was his role in piloting through the Act of Union in 1707 with Scotland. In the field of foreign affairs, his most important input was to ensure that reluctant politicians financed the War of Spanish Succession.

Harley became an adept non-party manager. He brought both moderate Tories and Whigs into government so that both parties would feel a sense of ownership of any decisions made. However, he fell out with Marlborough and Godolphin – both of whom shared his belief in being a non-party man – over his cousin Mrs Abigail Masham. For many years Queen Anne had as her favourite the highly influential Sarah Churchill, wife of Marlborough. There is little doubt that Sarah was the dominant personality in the relationship but her position was threatened and then taken over by Mrs Masham. Both Godolphin and Marlborough were concerned at this development and used their influence over the Queen to get Harley dismissed in February 1708.

By 1710, all those politicians in Westminster dissatisfied with the way politics was going rallied around Harley as he was seen as the natural leader of the opposition. Their primary criticisms were high taxation, corruption via the use of ‘placemen’ and the desire of the Whigs to line their own purses during the War of Spanish Succession which saw them deliberately prolong the war in the eyes of those who rallied behind Harley. Their beliefs matched the mood of a war weary nation. The trial of Henry Sacheverell acted as the spark to rally the poor of London. The so-called ‘Sacheverell Riots’ in London spurred Anne into action as no one wanted to confront the fear of social unrest. Between 1710 and 1711, Godolphin and Marlborough were dismissed and Harley led the government. A general election called at the same time returned a Tory majority to the Commons. Between 1710 and 1714, Harley was at the peak of his political powers.

Harley’s popularity increased still further after a failed assassination attempt on him by a French émigré called Antoine de Guisard on March 8th 1711. The fact that this attempt had been done by a foreigner brought Harley even more sympathy. Anne created Harley Earl of Oxford in May 1711. At home Harley, as Lord Treasurer, stabilised the economy and proved to the City that Tories were as able to do this as the Whigs. Abroad, he ended Britain’s involvement in the Spanish War of Succession in 1711 and pushed forward a peace process that culminated in the Treaty of Utrecht in 1713.

However, 1714 was the see the end of his political influence. This was caused by the issue of succession. Anne’s health had not been good for a number of years and the government with her support had pushed for a Hanovarian succession to her on her death. The Whigs were united in their support for the Elector George of Hanover. The Tories split into those who wanted him and those who did not. Harley bore the brunt of this disunity which was exploited by his main adversity - Viscount Bolingbroke. Unable to cope with such pressure – and never really a party man – Harley took to drinking more and more. He suffered accordingly and on more than one occasion was unintelligible in public. Anne dismissed him on July 27th 1714 – just five days before she died.

Rather than flee abroad, Harley stayed in England and was impeached. He spent two years in the Tower of London (1715 to 1717) before he was acquitted in July 1717.

Though Harley was allowed to remain a member of the House of Lords, he preferred to spend his time at his Hereford estates where he became a landlord interested in agricultural improvement. He also gained fame as a collector of important books and manuscripts.

Robert Harley, Earl of Oxford, died on May 21st 1724.

The South Sea Bubble

You can read about the first stock speculation and stock market crash and how this phenomenon affected the period here:
http://www.thesouthseabubble.com/



Travel Narratives

Swift posits Gulliver's Travels as an authentic travel narrative, which Captain Gulliver, the traveler, has published on the urging of his cousin, Sympson.  Swift has plenty of travel narratives to select as models for his narrative frame--and they continued well into the 18th century and beyond.  Some of them presented such exotic and incredible stories as "factual" accounts that gullible eighteenth-century readers, who had never ventured as far even as London (a magnet for the bizarre and exotic by this time), might be excused for believing Captain Gulliver's tales...or might they?
Here are some examples of travel narratives from the period that you and others in the class found:

(1) Thomas Gage’s “A New Survey of the West Indies being a Journal of Three Thousand and Three Hundred Miles within the Main Land of America.” The link to the thumbnails is below:
Hard to read in the original scan, but Google Books has a lot of the pages digitized from a later (copyrighted) version, so it’s more readable. I found this text interesting on many levels – one reason is that there’s a chapter on the Tlaxcallan Indians, so it references the Dryden play (Chapter X “wherein is first drawn the estate and condition of the great Town of Tlaxcallan, where the first Spaniards entered into the Empire of Mexico. Cortes first encounter with the Tlaxcaltecas, their league with him…”, p 60). Another is the obvious hatred by Gage of his Catholic religion and all its practices and what appears to be his increasing disgust with everything Catholic. There’s also a reference to “La Puebla de Los Angeles” twenty leagues from Mexico stating that “by reason of the good and wholesome air it daily increaseth with inhabitants” (p 50 on the Google Books version).  Interesting descriptions of the torturing done in the name of religion by the Catholic church; the descriptions of how the Indians looked and dressed; and descriptions of some of the “Europeanized” traditions of the native populations in their dances and ceremonies.

(2) A collection of voyages and travels, consisting of authentic writers in our own tongue, which have not before been collected in English, or have only been abridged in other Collections. And continued with others of note, that have published histories, Voyages, Travels, Journals or Discoveries in other Nations and Languages, relating to any part of the continent of Asia, Africa, America, Europe, or the Islands thereof, from the earliest Account to the present Time. Digested according to the parts o the world, to which they particularly relate: with historical introductions to each account, where thought necessary, containing either the Lives of their Authors or what else could be discovered and was supposed capable of entertaining and informing the curious Reader. And with great variety of cuts, prospects, Ruins, Maps, and Charts. Compiled from the curious and valuable library of the late Earl of Oxford. Interspersed and illustrated with Notes, Containing. Either a General Account of the Discovery of those Countries, or an Abstract of their Histories, Government, Trade, Religion, &c. collected from Original Papers, Letters, Charters, Letters Patents, Acts of Parliament, &c. not to be met with, and proper to explain many obscure Passages in other Collections of this Kind. ...  London : printed for and sold by Thomas Osborne of Gray's-Inn, MDCCXLV. [1745].

(3) The comical pilgrim; or, travels of a cynick philosopher, thro' the most wicked parts of the world, namely, England, Wales, Scotland, Ireland, and Holland. with His Merry Observations on the English Stage, Gaming-Houses, Poets, Beaux, Women, Courtiers, Politicians, and Plotters. Welsh Clergy, Gentry, and Customs. Scotch Manners, Religion, and Lawyers. Irish Ceremonies in their Marriages, Christenings, and Burials. And Dutch Government, Polity, and Trade. Being a general satyr on the vices and follies of the age. London,  1722. Eighteenth Century Collections Online. Gale. Georgia State Univ. 4 Oct. 2012
<http://find.galegroup.com.ezproxy.gsu.edu/ecco/infomark.do?&source=gale&prodId=ECCO&userGroupName=atla29738&tabID=T001&docId=CW3311416005&type=multipage&contentSet=ECCOArticles&version=1.0&docLevel=FASCIMILE>.

http://find.galegroup.com.ezproxy.gsu.edu/ecco/retrieve.do?sgHitCountType=None&sort=Author&tabID=T001&prodId=ECCO&resultListType=RESULT_LIST&searchId=R3&searchType=BasicSearchForm&currentPosition=34&qrySerId=Locale%28en%2C%2C%29%3AFQE%3D%28SU%2CNone%2C7%29travel+%3AAnd%3ALQE%3D%28BA%2CNone%2C14%29+2NEJ+Or+0LRK+%24&retrieveFormat=MULTIPAGE_DOCUMENT&userGroupName=atla29738&inPS=true&contentSet=ECCOArticles&&docId=CW3311416005&retrieveFormat=MULTIPAGE_DOCUMENT&docLevel=FASCIMILE&workId=CW3311416005&relevancePageBatch=CW111416004&showLOI=Yes&contentSet=&callistoContentSet=ECLL&docPage=article&hilite=y


(4) A Journal, with occasional remarks, made on a trip from Aleppo to Bussora, across the Grand Desart [sic] of Arabia by Henry Abbott.  In his preface he states that he is only going to focus on the most specific details of the journal.  He also apologizes for the inadequacies of the journal, not knowing that it was not intended for publication.  

This journal is similar to Gulliver's Travels in that it describes lands almost unknown to most of Europe.  Comically enough, he claims that he "will therefore endeavor, in as few words as [he] can, to give some outlines of it" (12)  Despite the narrators knowledge that Europeans know nothing of the Arab desert, he wants to keep his remarks short and sweet, a trope that Swift uses as well.

I would suggest reading selections alongside Swift's Travels to see stylistic similarities.

(5)
Mungo Park's Travels in the Interior Districts of Africa

http://find.galegroup.com/ecco/retrieve.do?sgHitCountType=None&scale=0.33&sort=Author&docLevel=FASCIMILE&prodId=ECCO&tabID=T001&searchId=R1&resultListType=RESULT_LIST&searchType=BasicSearchForm&currentPosition=1&qrySerId=Locale%28en%2C%2C%29%3AFQE%3D%28A0%2CNone%2C11%29park%2C+mungo%3AAnd%3ALQE%3D%28BA%2CNone%2C124%292NEF+Or+0LRH+Or+2NEK+Or+0LRL+Or+2NEI+Or+0LRI+Or+2NEJ+Or+0LRK+Or+2NEG+Or+0LRF+Or+2NEH+Or+0LRJ+Or+2NEM+Or+0LRN+Or+2NEL+Or+0LRM%24&retrieveFormat=MULTIPAGE_DOCUMENT&inPS=true&userGroupName=atla29738&docId=CW3307657650&currentPosition=1&workId=1233700900&relevancePageBatch=CW107657648&contentSet=ECCOArticles&callistoContentSet=ECCOArticles&resultListType=RESULT_LIST&reformatPage=N&retrieveFormat=MULTIPAGE_DOCUMENT&scale=0.33&pageIndex=4&orientation=&showLOI=Yes&quickSearchTerm=&stwFuzzy=&doDirectDocNumSearch=false&forRelevantNavigation=true

(6)
M. Adanson, A Voyage to Senegal, the Isle of Goree and the River Gambia.  London, 1759.
This is the narrative that I found re: 18th century that intrigued me. I was most interested in issues of blackness as "other".  This is only a partial representation of this narrative (it is 358 pages) but it details a travel narrative of a Frenchman to Senegal. It is mostly descriptive of the area but highlights Anderson's interaction with blacks as crude,basic yet hospitable. He had no read desire to interact with them apart from as "spectacles" of the natural habitat.

From Brandi for class 10/17:

Chloe Houston "Utopia, Dystopia or Anti-Utopia? Gulliver's Travels and the Utopian Mode of Discourse"

http://ehis.ebscohost.com.ezproxy.gsu.edu/eds/pdfviewer/pdfviewer?vid=3&hid=3&sid=aa037423-6a97-4d09-a442-b0172553be72@sessionmgr13

John B. Radner "The Fall and Decline: Gulliver's Travels and the Failure of Utopia"

http://ehis.ebscohost.com.ezproxy.gsu.edu/eds/detail?vid=6&hid=1&sid=aa037423-6a97-4d09-a442-b0172553be72%40sessionmgr13&bdata=JnNpdGU9ZWRzLWxpdmU%3d#db=wdh&AN=4113110

Selected Essays in English Literature, Peter Lang Publishing
"Horse Sense and Sensibility: Some Issues Concerning Utopian Understanding in Gulliver's Travels"

http://ehis.ebscohost.com.ezproxy.gsu.edu/eds/detail?vid=8&hid=121&sid=aa037423-6a97-4d09-a442-b0172553be72%40sessionmgr13&bdata=JnNpdGU9ZWRzLWxpdmU%3d#db=lfh&AN=19326429

Questions for class discussion:


1) How do we read Swift's Gulliver's Travels now in the twenty-first century? Do we see it more or less as Utopian discourse as technologies have progressed and led us to broader knowledge of other cultures both past and present?

2) Are the Houyhnhnms really the Utopian ideal, especially considering the other examples of moral characters in the text? Are they rendered absurd by Gulliver's obsession with their system of government, who himself in an effort to imitate them, falls into isolation from his family and own English society? Is Swift rendering them as the extreme, a warning to those who follow the ideal to it's absurd conclusion?

3) What do we make of the Houyhnhnms society based solely upon Reason? Is strict Reason followed throughout their culture in everything they do, and if so, then is it truly as idealistic as it is portrayed? How do we handle the justice of their slave-based society? How does their counsel regarding the Yahoos and Gulliver's fate represent decisions based upon reason alone or does it? If the counsel's logic is to be taken as the utopian ideal of reasoning, is it a desirable and/or applicable code of ethics?


Your suggested secondary sources:

Douglas Lane Patey, "Swift's Satire on 'Science and the Structure of Gulliver's Travels," ELH 58.4 (1991): 809-39.


In his essay entitled “Swift’s Satire on ‘Science’ and the Structure of Gulliver’s Travels” Douglas Lane Patey begins by differentiating between the eighteenth century definition of science and our modern version of the word, stating that in Swift’s time, they were just beginning to tease out the discipline of science as a separate arena of studies. In the eighteenth century the sciences were areas of thought which were not based solely on probability or conjecture. A thing was not defined in circular terms by its immediate effects, as with the example of the ancients defining opium being a soporific because taking it makes a person sleepy. Instead people were attempting to better understand the underlying laws of nature that provided said effects (813). Patey argues that Swift dislikes the modern sciences because of their excess in losing sight of “prudence,” given here as the recognition of the limitations of the human mind. Loss of practicality generates the same mistakes as the ancients and fails ultimately to progress forward, as seen through the Laputans where in their pushing of science to the extreme, they lose all sight of prudence to the point that even the applications of their calculations end up being failures. Though the Laputans are given to excel in math and music, their accomplishments upon paper become in application crooked houses and a city rendered almost entirely destitute. Patey demonstrates through Swift’s descriptions that the ideal methods of science should find a balance between scientific production and investigation; they should attempt to improve upon older methods yet accept the limitation that not all arenas of human life are to be known to the same level of exactness.
Next Patey moves on to demonstrate Swift’s use of the travel narrative, tracing how the experience of travel is similar to that of Lockean self-discovery and understanding as well as Swift’s method of “abstract[ing] away accidentals until we have a view of the essential” (826). Comparisons between bodies of vastly different sizes and shapes reveal the true essence of difference to lie in the capability of reasoning faculties not on the emphasis of certain pretensions like “beauty, power, or wisdom,” which are often mistakenly based solely on physical aspects (825). The essay moves back to analyze the necessity of the arts in life to provide what cannot be directly known by human knowledge. Patey argues Swift’s goal is to push culture as the ultimate defining point of the human race, giving culture to be a perpetual striving towards perfection, a need to progress, to explore, and to refuse to accept easy definitions which minimize and degrade human kind. He demonstrates that even through “quarrels with God” at the present state of affairs, people become prideful and stagnant, not using their reasoning faculties to find ways out of difficulties. Finally Patey discusses Swift’s sliding political and scientific views during the course of his lifetime which, like his critique, strive for progress through adaptation and balance.
Patey draws out well Swift’s ideals of combining progress with art, showing how Swift’s greatest critique lies with those who take any one line of thought to an extreme, become too sedate or prideful in their views, and fail to continue to find forward motion. Ultimately the goal is not to define anything as “either/or” or “certainty versus prudence” but finding a middle ground between poles or applying each line of thought/action where it is best applicable. The greatest difficulties lie in defining any of the viewpoints in the text as tried and true; as often as Swift asserts one argument, he then undercuts it. As much as the science of the Laputans is downgraded, there is no critique against their deductions of the movement of the heavenly bodies beyond their losing sight of day to day experiences and challenges. Swift does not seem here to give fault with their explorations of the celestial bodies but with their lack of balance of these discoveries with “closer to home” concerns. The argument that all must be a balance, however, gives no clear method of progress forward because it leaves a great deal of uncertainty which must be explored. There is little way of knowing which arena in life must have more certainty applied to it and which ought to be left more to prudence until it is tested with both. The challenge is to recognize before it is too late, before degeneration begins to occur, when to cease and desist applying too much scientific application or too much prudence to the result of excess pride. 

 

Analysis of Fereshteh Zangenehpour’s Article “The Essential Displacement: Lordship and Sovereignty in Aphra Behn’s Oroonoko, or The Royal Slave[1]
Fereshteh Zangenehpour’s deconstruction article “The Essential Displacement: Lordship and Sovereignty in Aphra Behn’s Oroonoko, or The Royal Slave” successfully argues that Oroonoko’s paradoxical position as the Royal Slave […] [results in] the erasure and silencing of dialectical continuity [in the novella]” (87).  This essay attempts to answer the questions of Oroonoko’s identity through the heuristic of Derrida and Hegel, specifically regarding the identity of the Self and Other.  Indeed, Zangenehpour determines Oroonoko to not only represent the role of a slave, but also that of a leader.  The dichotomy between lordship and bondage is prevalent throughout the work, but, as Zangenehpour argues, Oroonoko experiences a “failure to recognize and acknowledge his contradictory situation,” resulting in a confused, broken Oroonoko (87).
Zangenehpour resourcefully consults two distinct types of evidence throughout the article.  First, she heavily relies upon the writings of Hegel, Bataille, and Derrida in determining the relationship between lordship and sovereignty—two concepts that are generally at odds for Oroonoko’s character—providing a solid theoretical foundation for the close reading to follow.  Using the logical arguments already set forth by Derrida and Bataille, Zangenehpour determines that Oroonoko is equally consumed with sovereignty and lordship (88), but she argues that lordship is the more dominant of the two forces due to Oroonoko’s role in the slave revolt.  Oroonoko, she argues using these authors’ work on dialectical dilemmas, is unlikely to experience much of a slave’s mentality because of his upbringing in his homeland (88).  The “repressed consciousness [of a slave] has no essential reality” in Oroonoko’s psyche, but when it intersects with his dominant consciousness of a prince, “both consider each other as common objects [and] they have to defend or protect themselves” (90). 
Zangenehpour continues her analysis of Hegels’s master-slave dialectic, claiming that Oroonoko’s situation is particularly precarious because of “the colour of his skin” (90).  In Surinam, Oroonoko’s skin color automatically determines his role as a slave within the society.  After providing extensive amount of background information, Zangenehpour arrives at what I find to be his most clear thesis statement: she “[studies] Oroonoko’s inner perplexity and [witnesses] how he negotiates between his two diverse selves throughout his life in Surinam” (90-91).
As I mention above, Zangenehpour consults two types of evidence.  In addition to the theoretical work already discussed, she relies on a plentitude of primary source evidence.  In handling the novella itself, Zangenehpour quite helpfully breaks the novella into three distinct sections: Oroonoko’s status as a prince in Africa, his reduction to a slave in Surinam, and his organization of the slave revolt (91). Zangenehpour’s evidence clearly suggests that Oroonoko is of nobility and should be viewed as a Self by the reader, rather than an Other, because the narrator is a noble, white woman (92).  Oroonoko is reduced, however, to the low rank of a slave once he is captured by a white slave trader through deceit (93).  This slavery, Zangenehpour argues, “gives rise to a complex dilemma” (93).  Oroonoko has a desire to be recognized as an equal by the whites because of his noble character, regardless of his skin color. Zangenehpour cleverly suggests that Oroonoko, now removed from his lordship, continues to act as a lord with regard to his slave revolts, which upsets the political system (93-94).  In the third part, the novella becomes even more complicated.  Oroonoko, who is at this point simulating lordship, now fears for Imoinda’s child.  This child, Zangenehpour notes, will be born into slavery and forced to relive the trials that Oroonoko experiences.  Oroonoko’s master-self takes over once more in the revolt, and he returns to his former glory as a prince, at least until the revolt is quelled (94-95).  Upon Oroonoko’s capture, he is bound and fastened before execution, reducing him to the rank of a slave once more (97).
With regard to organization, the essay is as successful with structure as it is with evidence.  Zangenehpour provides a clear introduction to the topic in the first sentence, including all of the words that she continues to reference in the first sentence.  After a clear statement of her thesis, provides grounding in deconstruction by summarizing the key arguments of the texts she consults throughout the work.  This is very effective, I find, because she remains focused on the textual evidence after explaining the theory, providing clarity.  The textual evidence rightly follows the chronology of the novella.  She then ends with a strong conclusion, leaving no unanswered questions. 
At one point seemingly as an aside, Zangenehpour returns to Hegel and Derrida to determine Oroonoko’s Self-conscious motivation for organizing the revolt, meaning that (95).  I do not find the paragraph relevant since Zangenehpour argues earlier that Oroonoko’s actions are only to save his child from being born into the same situation.  Further analysis seems to contradict his existing argument.  Aside from this small qualm, I find that Zangenehpour’s article is entirely effective and successful in providing a deconstructive analysis of Oroonoko.  Perhaps he could have including some consultation of other scholars’ work on similar subjects, though.  There is a definite lacking of any explanation for how this work enters into the critical conversation of deconstruction in Oroonoko.


[1] Zangenehpour, Fereshteh. “The Essential Displacement: Lordship and Sovereignty in Aphra Behn’s Oroonoko, or The Royal Slave.Nordic Journal English Studies 9.1 (2010): 86-99. MLAIB. Web. 15 Sept. 2012.


7 comments:

  1. The wonders of a journey consist far more of such intangible experiences and unexpected situations than of factual things and events of material reality.
    Flights to Addis Ababa
    Cheap Flights to Addis Ababa
    Cheap Air Tickets to Addis Ababa

    ReplyDelete
  2. A few interesting reactions to GT:

    Samuel Johnson said of it, "When once you have thought of big men and little men, it is very easy to do all the rest" and considered it s minor work of Swift's. He also said it was a "production so new and strange, that it filled the reader with mingled emotions of merriment and amazement. It was received with such avidity, that the price of the first edition was raised before the second could be made; and it was read by the high and the low, the learned and illiterate. Criticism was for a while lost in wonder; no rules of judgment were applied to a book written in open defiance of truth and regularity. But when distinctions came to be made, the part which gave the least pleasure was Laputa, and that which gave the most disgust was the Houyhnhnms."

    This thought is echoed by Samuel Taylor Coleridge, who wrote, "I would rank Lilliput Swift's highest achievement, next Brobdingnag; and I would expunge Laputa altogether. It is a wretched abortion, the product of spleen and self-conceit."

    ReplyDelete
  3. Thanks, Zack. Some of the reception history is covered in the appendices of Allan Ingram's Broadview edition. Sam Johnson's proclamations (on pretty much everything) are in themselves worthy of critical study.

    ReplyDelete
  4. I found an online edition of Popes poem written from the perspective of Mary Gulliver. Definitely worth reading! http://www4.ncsu.edu/~leila/alpope.htm

    Some articles I enjoyed:

    F.R. Leavis' "The Irony of Swift":

    "The clean skin of the Houyhnhnms, in short, is stretched over a void; instincts, emotions, an life, which complicate the problem of cleanliness and decency, are left for the Yahoos with the dirt and the indecorum. Reason, Truth and Nature serve instead; the Houyhnhnms (who scorn metaphysics) find them inadequate. Swift too scorned metaphysics, and never found anything better to contend for than a skin, a surface, an outward show.
    ...
    Swift did his best for the Houyhnhnms, and they may have all the reason, but the Yahoos have all the life."


    Andre Breton's "Swift and Black Humor":

    "When it comes to black humor, everything designates him as the true initiator. In fact, it is impossible to coordinate the fugitive traces of this kind of humor before him, not even in Heraclitus and the Cynics or in the works of the Elizabethan dramatic poets. Swift's incontestable originality, the perfect untiy of his production viewed from the angle of the very special and almost unprecedented emotion it elicits, the unsurpassable character, from this same viewpoint, of his many varied successes historically justify his being presented as the first black humorist.
    ...
    From one end of his life to the other, his misanthropy was the only disposition that never altered, and that events never belied."

    Penelope Wilson's "Feminism and the Augustans: Some Readings and Problems":

    "If feminism has--until very recently--left Augustan satire alone, it is partly no doubt because it can expect few rewards from an area which offers more obvious scope for recrimination than for critical insight.

    ...

    But despite the real need to free readings from the pull of misogyny, there are acute problems for feminism in these uncongenial waters. The political importance of a more consciously resistant reading in this case seems to remain, disappointingly, out of all proportion to its usefulness as a critical tool. The potential creativity of entry into the text from the margins too easily loses itself in a righteous cul-de-sac of recrimination or in a self-generating process of elaboration on the 'position' of feminist theory."
    ...
    Is the author of Gulliver's Travels still best understood as an Old or Real Whig even though Old Whig principles and rhetoric were by 1726 appropriated by Jacobites and Tories? Despite the contingency and nominalism of political argument in contemporary pamphlet and periodical literature, some real differences between 'Old Whig' and 'Tory' political positions ca be registered. Considering some of the differences, it is evident that Swift's politics are 'Tory.'"

    ReplyDelete
  5. George Orwell's "Politics vs. Literature: An Examination of Gulliver's Travels":
    It is necessary, for instance, that [Gulliver] should appear sensible in Part 1 and at least intermittently silly in Part II, because in both books the essential manoeuvre is the same, i.e. to make the human being look ridiculous by imagining him as a creature six inches high.
    ...
    Swift's physical repulsion from humanity is certainly real enough, but one has the feeling that his debunking of human grandeur, his diatribes against lords, politicians, court favorites, etc. has mainly a local application and springs from the fact that he belonged to the unsuccessful party. He denounces injustice and oppression, bt he gives no evidence of liking democracy.
    ...
    Swift shows no signs of haing any religious beliefs, at least in the ordinary sense of the words. He does not appear to believe seriously in life after death, and his idea of goodness is bound up in republicanism, love of liberty, courage, 'benevolence' (meaning in effect public spirit, 'reason' and other pagan qualities.
    ...
    But are we to infer from all this that Swift was first and foremost an enemy of tyranny and a champion of free intelligence? No: his own views, so far as one can discern them, are not markedly liberal. No doubt he hates lords, kings, bishops, generals, ladies of fashion, orders, titles and flummery generally; but he does not seem to think better of the common people than of their rulers, or to be in favor of increased social equality, or to be enthusiastic about representative institutions.
    ...
    The Houyhnhnms, we are told, are unanimous on almost all subjects. The only question they have ever discussed was how to deal with the Yahoos. Otherwise there was no room for disagreement among them, because the truth is always either self-evident, or else it is undiscoverable and unimportant. They apparently had no word for 'opinion' in their language, and in their conversations there was no 'difference of sentiments.' They had reached, in fact, the highest stage of totalirarian organisation, the stage where conformity has become so general that there is no need for a police force. Swift approves of this kind of thing because among his many gifts neither curiosity nor good-nature was included. Disagreement would always seem to him sheer perversity.
    ...
    Swift was presumably impotent, and had an exaggerated horror of human dung: he also though about it incessantly, as is evident throughout his works. Such people are not likely to enjoy even the small amount of happiness that falls to most human beings, and, from obvious motives, are not likely to admit that earthly life is capable of much improvement. Their incuriosity, and hence their intolerance, spring from the same root.
    ...
    The Houyhnhnms, creatures without a history, continue for generation after generation to live prudently, maintaining their population at exactly the same level, avoiding all passion, suffering from no diseases, meeting death indifferently, training up their young in the same principles--and all for what? In order that the same process may continue indefinitely. The notions that life here and now is worth living, or that it could be made worth living, or that it must be sacrificed for some future good, are all absent. The dreary world of the Houyhnhnms was about as good a Utopia as Swift could construct, granting that he neither believed in a 'next world' nor could get any pleasure out of certain normal activities. But it is not really set up as something desirable in itself, but as the justification for another attack on humanity. The aim, as usual, is to humiliate Man by reminding him that he is weak and ridiculous, and above all that he stinks; and the ultimate motive, probably, is a kind of envy, the envy of the ghost for the living, of the man who knows he cannot be happy for the others who--so he fears--may be a little happier than himself.
    ...

    ReplyDelete
  6. Supposing that there is such a thing as good art or bad art, then the goodness or badness must reside in the work of art itself--not independently of the observer, indeed, but independently of the mood of the observer...An aesthetic judgment can be upset...disastrously by political or moral disagreement. If a book angers, wounds or alarms you, then you will not enjoy it, whatever its merits may be. If it seems to you a really pernicious book, likely to influence other people in some undesirable way, then you will probably construct an aesthetic theory to show that it has no merits. Current literary criticism consists quite largely of this kind of dodging to and fro between two sets of standards. And yet the opposite process can also happen: enjoyment can overwhelm disapproval, even though one clearly recognises that one is enjoying something inimical. Swift, whose world-view is so peculiarly unacceptable, but who is nevertheless an extremely popular writer, is a good instance of this. Why is it that we don't mind being called Yahoos, although firmly convinced that we are not Yahoos?
    ...
    The explanation must be that Swift's world-view is felt to be not altogether false--or it would probably be more accurate to say, not false all the time. Swift is a diseased writer. He remains permenantly in a depressed mood which in most people is only intermittant, rather as though someone suffering from jaundice or the after-effects of influenza should have the energy to write books. But we all know that mood, and something in us responds to the expression of it.
    ...
    Part of our mids--in any normal person it is the dominant part--believes that man is a noble animal and life is worth living: but there is also a sort of inner self which at least intermittantly stands aghast at the horror of existence. In the queerest way, pleasure a disgust are linked together. The human body is beautiful: it is also repulsive and ridiculous,a fact which can be verified at any swimming pool. The sexual organs are objects of desire and also of loathing, so much so that in many languages, if not in all languages, their names are used as words of abuse...A child, when it is past the infantile stage but still looking at the world with fresh eyes, is moved by horror almost as often as by wonder--horror of snot and spittle, the dying toad full of maggots, the sweaty smell of grown-ups, of the dogs' excrement on the pavement, the hideousness of old men, with their bald heads and bulbous noses. In his endless harping on disease, dirt and deformity, Swift is not actually inventing anything, he is merely leaving something out...His attitude is in effect the Christian attitude, minus the bribe of the 'next world.'
    ...
    It is often argued, at least by people who admit the importance of subject matter, that a book cannot be 'good' if it expresses a palpably false view of life....This ignores the fact that throughout history a similar struggle between progress and reaction has been raging, and that the best books of any one age have always been written from several different viewpoints, some of them palpably more flase than others In so far as the writer is a propogandist, the most one can ask of him is that he shall genuinely believe what he is saying, and that it shall not be something blazingly silly...The views that a writer holds must be compatible with sanity, in the medical sense, and with the power of continuous thought: beyond that what we ask of him is talent, which is probably another name for conviction."

    ReplyDelete
  7. Also interesting was R.S. Crane's "The Houyhnhnms, the Yahoos, and the History of Ideas," which argues that Swift's "horse as rational animal" is a deliberate reversal of the popular Porphyryean use of man vs. horse to indicate man's rationality, Claude Rawson's "Swift's I Narrators," which notes how Gulliver's post-Houyhnhnm position in writing his fictional memoir both breaks down and also influences our reading of it, and Jenny Mezciems' essay on Swift and More's different Utopias, in which she notes the failure of the Houyhnhnms to be able to use imagination or hypotheticals as a serious flaw in their "utopia."

    Ian Higgins' "Swift's Politics":
    Swift intended Gulliver's Travels as a polemical act against the Whig government and a satire on contemporary European civilization and the vices and follies of humanity.
    ...
    Sometimes [Swift] averred that there was no real difference between the essential principles of Whig and Tory and that he was moderate and bipartisan. He wrote, 'I hardly ever saw a Whig and a Tory together, whom I could not immediately reconcile when I made them explain themselves.'
    ...
    The exegesis of Swift's political principles and party political allegiance is a matter of continuin disagreemtn in modern Swift studies. Essentally there are three basic ad contradictory accounts of Swift's politics. One position is that Swift is a post-Revolutionary Tory who was temporarily allied by circumstance to the Whigs. The case for Swift as a Tory in politics and ecclesiology has been advanced principally and recently in the work of E.P. Lock. A second position in Swift studies tends to see Swift as a paradoxical, idiosyncratic political figure whose political attitudes include elements from Tory and Whig extremes of contemporary political argument; that there are conservative Tory and reactionary and radical WHig and libertarian strands in his political ideology. This second position argues that it is probably a futile exercise to try ti site Swift in the terrain of post-Revolution party politics or that both 'Whig' and 'Tory' descriptions of Swift are appropriate. A third view is that Swift is essentially a Whig in state politics and remained so despite his 'conversion' to the predominantly Tory administration of 1710-14. This view, which can be found stated or expounded in the work of many distinguished Swiftians, would appear to be the present scholarly orthodoxy although the critical shorthand 'Tory satirists' applied to Swift anf the Scriblerian circle still has currency. The Whig case for Swift squares with a literal reading of Swift's repeated profession that he was 'a Whig in politics' although a 'High-churchman' in religion; that he 'of the old Whig principles, without the modern articles and refinements.' Swift's hostility to 'modern whiggery' and particularly to the Walpolean regime is not contested but it is argued that his opposition to the modern Whig party leadership reflects his fundamental Whig principles rather than disaffected Tory politics."

    ReplyDelete