Sunday, September 2, 2012

Margaret Cavendish, The Blazing World

From Nancy, one of the useful entries in Pepys's diary about Margaret Cavendish:
http://www.pepysdiary.com/archive/1667/04/11/
Having received this money I home with Balty and it, and then abroad by coach with my wife and set her down at her father’s, and I to White Hall, thinking there to have seen the Duchess of Newcastle’s coming this night to Court, to make a visit to the Queene, the King having been with her yesterday, to make her a visit since her coming to town. The whole story of this lady is a romance, and all she do is romantick. Her footmen in velvet coats, and herself in an antique dress, as they say; and was the other day at her own play, “The Humourous Lovers;” the most ridiculous thing that ever was wrote, but yet she and her Lord mightily pleased with it; and she, at the end, made her respects to the players from her box, and did give them thanks. There is as much expectation of her coming to Court, that so people may come to see her, as if it were the Queen of Sheba [L&M say “Queen of Sweden”. P.G.]; but I lost my labour, for she did not come this night.

Pepys also said:
(March 18, 1668) Thence home, and there, in favour to my eyes, stayed at home, reading the ridiculous History of my Lord Newcastle, wrote by his wife, which shews her to be a mad, conceited, ridiculous woman, and he an asse to suffer her to write what she writes to him, and of him.

(May 30, 1667) After dinner I walked to Arundell House, the way very dusty, the day of meeting of the Society being changed from Wednesday to Thursday, which I knew not before, because the Wednesday is a Council- day, and several of the Council are of the Society, and would come but for their attending the King at Council; where I find much company, indeed very much company, in expectation of the Duchesse of Newcastle, who had desired to be invited to the Society; and was, after much debate, pro and con., it seems many being against it; and we do believe the town will be full of ballads of it. Anon comes the Duchesse with her women attending her; among others, the Ferabosco, of whom so much talk is that her lady would bid her show her face and kill the gallants. She is indeed black, and hath good black little eyes, but otherwise but a very ordinary woman I do think, but they say sings well. The Duchesse hath been a good, comely woman; but her dress so antick, and her deportment so ordinary, that I do not like her at all, nor did I hear her say any thing that was worth hearing, but that she was full of admiration, all admiration. Several fine experiments were shown her of colours, loadstones, microscopes, and of liquors among others, of one that did, while she was there, turn a piece of roasted mutton into pure blood, which was very rare. Here was Mrs. Moore [L&M say “Mr. Moore”. P.G.] of Cambridge, whom I had not seen before, and I was glad to see her; as also a very pretty black boy that run up and down the room, somebody’s child in Arundell House. After they had shown her many experiments, and she cried still she was full of admiration, she departed, being led out and in by several Lords that were there; among others Lord George Barkeley and Earl of Carlisle, and a very pretty young man, the Duke of Somerset. She gone, I by coach home, and there busy at my letters till night, and then with my wife in the evening singing with her in the garden with great pleasure, and so home to supper and to bed. http://www.pepysdiary.com/archive/1667/05/30/

(May 10, 1667) Then to my Lord Treasurer’s, but missed Sir Ph. Warwicke, and so back again, and drove hard towards Clerkenwell,1 thinking to have overtaken my Lady Newcastle, whom I saw before us in her coach, with 100 boys and girls running looking upon her but I could not: and so she got home before I could come up to her. But I will get a time to see her.

May 1, 1667)  Thence Sir W. Pen and I in his coach, Tiburne way, into the Park, where a horrid dust, and number of coaches, without pleasure or order. That which we, and almost all went for, was to see my Lady Newcastle; which we could not, she being followed and crowded upon by coaches all the way she went, that nobody could come near her; only I could see she was in a large black coach, adorned with silver instead of gold, and so white curtains, and every thing black and white, and herself in her cap, but other parts I could not make [out]. But that which I did see, and wonder at with reason, was to find Pegg Pen in a new coach, with only her husband’s pretty sister with her, both patched and very fine, and in much the finest coach in the park, and I think that ever I did see one or other, for neatness and richness in gold, and everything that is noble. My Lady Castlemayne, the King, my Lord St. Albans, nor Mr. Jermyn, have so neat a coach, that ever I saw. And, Lord! to have them have this, and nothing else that is correspondent, is to me one of the most ridiculous sights that ever I did see, though her present dress was well enough; but to live in the condition they do at home, and be abroad in this coach, astonishes me.

(April 26, 1667)  This done Sir W. Batten and I back again to London, and in the way met my Lady Newcastle going with her coaches and footmen all in velvet: herself, whom I never saw before, as I have heard her often described, for all the town-talk is now-a-days of her extravagancies, with her velvetcap, her hair about her ears; many black patches, because of pimples about her mouth; naked-necked, without any thing about it, and a black just-au-corps. She seemed to me a very comely woman: but I hope to see more of her on Mayday. My mind is mightily of late upon a coach.

(March 30, 1667)  Up, and the French periwigg maker of whom I bought two yesterday comes with them, and I am very well pleased with them. So to the office, where all the morning. At noon home to dinner, and thence with my wife’s knowledge and leave did by coach go see the silly play of my Lady Newcastle’s, called “The Humourous Lovers;” the most silly thing that ever come upon a stage. I was sick to see it, but yet would not but have seen it, that I might the better understand her. Here I spied Knipp and Betty, of the King’s house, and sent Knipp oranges, but, having little money about me, did not offer to carry them abroad, which otherwise I had, I fear, been tempted to.

Pepys on anatomy including circulation of the blood, which fascinated Margaret Cavendish too:

Friday 27 February 1662/63
Up and to my office, whither several persons came to me about office business. About 11 o’clock, Commissioner Pett and I walked to Chyrurgeon’s Hall (we being all invited thither, and promised to dine there); where we were led into the Theatre; and by and by comes the reader, Dr. Tearne, with the Master and Company, in a very handsome manner: and all being settled, he begun his lecture, this being the second upon the kidneys, ureters, &c., which was very fine; and his discourse being ended, we walked into the Hall, and there being great store of company, we had a fine dinner and good learned company, many Doctors of Phisique, and we used with extraordinary great respect. Among other observables we drank the King’s health out of a gilt cup given by King Henry VIII. to this Company, with bells hanging at it, which every man is to ring by shaking after he hath drunk up the whole cup. There is also a very excellent piece of the King, done by Holbein, stands up in the Hall, with the officers of the Company kneeling to him to receive their Charter. After dinner Dr. Scarborough took some of his friends, and I went along with them, to see the body alone, which we did, which was a lusty fellow, a seaman, that was hanged for a robbery. I did touch the dead body with my bare hand: it felt cold, but methought it was a very unpleasant sight. It seems one Dillon, of a great family, was, after much endeavours to have saved him, hanged with a silken halter this Sessions (of his own preparing), not for honour only, but it seems, it being soft and sleek, it do slip close and kills, that is, strangles presently: whereas, a stiff one do not come so close together, and so the party may live the longer before killed. But all the Doctors at table conclude, that there is no pain at all in hanging, for that it do stop the circulation of the blood; and so stops all sense and motion in an instant. Thence we went into a private room, where I perceive they prepare the bodies, and there were the kidneys, ureters [&c.], upon which he read to-day, and Dr. Scarborough upon my desire and the company’s did show very clearly the manner of the disease of the stone and the cutting and all other questions that I could think of … [Poor Mr. Wheatley could not even stand a medical lecture on physiology. D.W.] how the water [comes] into the bladder through the three skins or coats just as poor Dr. Jolly has heretofore told me. Thence with great satisfaction to me back to the Company, where I heard good discourse, and so to the afternoon Lecture upon the heart and lungs, &c., and that being done we broke up, took leave, and back to the office, we two, Sir W. Batten, who dined here also, being gone before. Here late, and to Sir W. Batten’s to speak upon some business, where I found Sir J. Minnes pretty well fuddled I thought: he took me aside to tell me how being at my Lord Chancellor’s to-day, my Lord told him that there was a Great Seal passing for Sir W. Pen, through the impossibility of the Comptroller’s duty to be performed by one man; to be as it were joynt-comptroller with him, at which he is stark mad; and swears he will give up his place, and do rail at Sir W. Pen the cruellest; he I made shift to encourage as much as I could, but it pleased me heartily to hear him rail against him, so that I do see thoroughly that they are not like to be great friends, for he cries out against him for his house and yard and God knows what. For my part, I do hope, when all is done, that my following my business will keep me secure against all their envys. But to see how the old man do strut, and swear that he understands all his duty as easily as crack a nut, and easier, he told my Lord Chancellor, for his teeth are gone; and that he understands it as well as any man in England; and that he will never leave to record that he should be said to be unable to do his duty alone; though, God knows, he cannot do it more than a child. All this I am glad to see fall out between them and myself safe, and yet I hope the King’s service well done for all this, for I would not that should be hindered by any of our private differences. So to my office, and then home to supper and to bed.

Robert Hooke's Micrographia

 
Here is a UC Berkeley site that summarizes Hooke's key work on microscopes and has further links:
http://www.ucmp.berkeley.edu/history/hooke.html

An article on Newton, the Royal Society, and the telescope that we have in J-STOR (you will need to be logged in through GSU to access this):

http://www.jstor.org.ezproxy.gsu.edu/stable/531836?&Search=yes&searchText=Society%27s&searchText=Telescope&searchText=Royal&searchText=Newton&searchText=Account&list=hide&searchUri=%2Faction%2FdoBasicSearch%3FQuery%3DAn%2BAccount%2Bof%2Bthe%2BRoyal%2BSociety%2527s%2BNewton%2BTelescope%26acc%3Don%26wc%3Don&prevSearch=&item=1&ttl=381&returnArticleService=showFullText
 Or put the search terms "An Account of the Royal Society's Newton Telescope" in the search bar of J-STOR.

If you are interested in the empirical science behind Blazing World you can also search in J-STOR, MLA etc for "Royal Society 1600-1699" or "Royal Society Margaret Cavendish"

Some secondary source suggestions from Nancy:

Royalist, Romancist, Racialist: Rank, Gender, and Race in the Science and Fiction of Margaret Cavendish

(This is  Iyengar, Sujata,  English Literary History 69 (3): 649-72, 2001




http://www.jstor.org/stable/30032037?seq=4


Margaret Cavendish among the prophets: performance ideologies and gender in and after the english civil war
(This is Wiseman, Susan, Women's Writing 6: 95-111, 1999)




http://www.tandfonline.com/doi/pdf/10.1080/09699089900200062


Cavendish's Poems 

 

 

The weight of Atomes. If Atomes are as small, as small can bee, 
They must in quantity of Matter all agree: 
And if consisting Matter of the same (be right,) 
Then every Atome must weigh just alike. 
Thus Quantity, Quality and Weight, all 
Together meets in every Atome small. 

The joyning of severall Figur'd Atomes make other Figures.  Severall Figur'd Atomes well agreeing, 
When joyn'd, do give another Figure being. 
For as those Figures joyned, severall waies, 
The Fabrick of each severall Creature raise. 

_______________ 
Line 1.  Severall Figur'd: distinctively shaped.
Line 2.  Figure: shape, form
Line 4.  Severall: distinct, individual.

A World in an Eare-Ring. 

An Eare-ring round may well a Zodiacke bee, 
Where in a Sun goeth round, and we not see. 
And Planets seven about that Sun may move, 
And Hee stand still, as some wise men would prove. 
And fixed Stars, like twinkling Diamonds, plac'd 
About this Eare-ring, which a World is vast. 
That same which doth the Eare-ring hold, the hole
Is that, which we do call the Pole
There nipping Frosts may be, and Winter cold, 
Yet never on the Ladies Eare take hold.                                   10 
And Lightnings, Thunder, and great Winds may blow 
Within this Eare-ring, yet the Eare not know. 
There Seas may ebb, and flow, where Fishes swim, 
And Islands be, where Spices grow therein. 
There Christall Rocks hang dangling at each Eare
And Golden Mines as Jewels may they weare. 
There Earth-quakes be, which Mountains vast downe fling, 
And yet nere stir the Ladies Eare, nor Ring
There Meadowes bee, and Pastures fresh, and greene
And Cattell feed, and yet be never seene:                                  20 
And Gardens fresh, and Birds which sweetly sing, 
Although we heare them not in an Eare-ring
There Night, and Day, and Heat, and Cold, and so 
May Life, and Death, and Young, and Old, still grow. 
Thus Youth may spring, and severall Ages dye, 
Great Plagues may be, and no Infections nigh, 
There Cityes bee, and stately Houses built, 
Their inside gaye, and finely may be gilt. 
There Churches bee, and Priests to teach therein, 
And Steeple too, yet heare the Bells not ring.                            30 
From thence may pious Teares to Heaven run, 
And yet the Eare not know which way they're gone. 
There Markets bee, and things both bought, and sold, 
Know not the price, nor how the Markets hold. 
There Governours do rule, and Kings do Reigne, 
And Battels fought, where many may be slaine. 
And all within the Compasse of this Ring
And yet not tidings to the Wearer bring. 
Within the Ring wise Counsellors may sit, 
And yet the Eare not one wise word may get.                           40 
There may be dancing all Night at a Ball
And yet the Eare be not disturb'd at all. 
There Rivals Duels fight, where some are slaine; 
There Lovers mourne, yet heare them not complaine. 
And Death may dig a Lovers Grave, thus were 
A Lover Dead, in a Faire Ladies Eare
But when the Ring is broke, the World is done, 
Then Lovers they into Elysium run.



Here is a BIOGRAPHICAL article from the Encyclopedia of World Biography. Copyright 2010 The Gale Group, Inc. All rights reserved:

Margaret Lucas Cavendish Biography

Margaret Cavendish (1623-1673) was one of the first prolific female science writers. As the author of approximately 14 scientific or quasi-scientific books, she helped to popularize some of the most important ideas of the scientific revolution, including the competing vitalistic and mechanistic natural philosophies and atomism. A flamboyant and eccentric woman, Cavendish was the most visible of the "scientific ladies" of the seventeenth century.
Margaret Lucas was born into a life of luxury near Colchester, England, in 1623, the youngest of eight children of Sir Thomas Lucas. She was educated informally at home. At the age of eighteen, she left her sheltered life to become Maid of Honor to Queen Henrietta Maria, wife of Charles I, accompanying the queen into exile in France following the defeat of the royalists in the civil war. There she fell in love with and married William Cavendish, the Duke of Newcastle, a 52 year-old widower, who had been commander of the royalist forces in the north of England. Joining other exiled royalists in Antwerp, the couple rented the mansion of the artist Rubens. Margaret Cavendish was first exposed to science in their informal salon society, "The Newcastle Circle," which included the philosophers Thomas Hobbes, René Descartes, and Pierre Gassendi. She visited England in 1651-52 to try to collect revenues from the Newcastle estate to satisfy their foreign creditors. It was at this time that Cavendish first gained her reputation for extravagant dress and manners, as well as for her beauty and her bizarre poetry.

Published Original Natural Philosophy

Cavendish prided herself on her originality and boasted that her ideas were the products of her own imagination, not derived from the writings of others. Cavendish's first anthology, Poems, and Fancies, included the earliest version of her natural philosophy. Although English atomic theory in the seventeenth century attempted to explain all natural phenomena as matter in motion, in Cavendish's philosophy all atoms contained the same amount of matter but differed in size and shape; thus, earth atoms were square, water particles were round, atoms of air were long, and fire atoms were sharp. This led to her humoral theory of disease, wherein illness was due to fighting between atoms or an overabundance of one atomic shape. However in her second volume, Philosophical Fancies, published later in the same year, Cavendish already had disavowed her own atomic theory. By 1663, when she published Philosophical and Physical Opinions, she had decided that if atoms were "Animated Matter," then they would have "Free-will and Liberty" and thus would always be at war with one another and unable to cooperate in the creation of complex organisms and minerals. Nevertheless, Cavendish continued to view all matter as composed of one material, animate and intelligent, in contrast to the Cartesian view of a mechanistic universe.

Challenged Other Scientists

Cavendish and her husband returned to England with the restoration of the monarchy in 1660 and, for the first time, she began to study the works of other scientists. Finding herself in disagreement with most of them, she wrote Philosophical Letters: or, Modest Reflections upon some Opinions in Natural Philosophy, maintained by several Famous and Learned Authors of this Age, Expressed by way of Letters in 1664. Cavendish sent copies of this work, along with Philosophical and Physical Opinions, by special messenger to the most famous scientists and celebrities of the day. In 1666 and again in 1668, she published Observations upon Experimental Philosophy, a response to Robert Hooke's Micrographia, in which she attacked the use of recently-developed microscopes and telescopes as leading to false observations and interpretations of the natural world. Included in the same volume with Observations was The Blazing World was a semi-scientific utopian romance, in which Cavendish declared herself "Margaret the First."

Invited to the Royal Society

More than anything else, Cavendish yearned for the recognition of the scientific community. She presented the universities of Oxford and Cambridge with each of her publications and she ordered a Latin index to accompany the writings she presented to the University of Leyden, hoping thereby that her work would be utilized by European scholars.
After much debate among the membership of the Royal Society of London, Cavendish became the first woman invited to visit the prestigious institution, although the controversy had more to due with her notoriety than with her sex. On May 30, 1667, Cavendish arrived with a large retinue of attendants and watched as Robert Boyle and Robert Hooke weighed air, dissolved mutton in sulfuric acid, and conducted various other experiments. It was a major advance for the scientific lady and a personal triumph for Cavendish.
Cavendish published the final revision of her Philosophical and Physical Opinions, entitled Grounds of Natural Philosophy, in 1668. Significantly more modest than her previous works, in this volume Cavendish presented her views somewhat tentatively and retracted some of her earlier, more extravagant claims. Cavendish acted as her own physician, and her self-inflicted prescriptions, purgings, and bleedings resulted in the rapid deterioration of her health. She died in 1673 and was buried in Westminster Abbey.
Although her writings remained well outside the mainstream of seventeenth-century science, Cavendish's efforts were of major significance. She helped to popularize many of the ideas of the scientific revolution and she was one of the first natural philosophers to argue that theology was outside the parameters of scientific inquiry. Furthermore, her work and her prominence as England's first recognized woman scientist argued strongly for the education of women and for their involvement in scientific pursuits. In addition to her scientific writings, Cavendish published a book of speeches, a volume of poetry, and a large number of plays. Several of the latter, particularly The Female Academy, included learned women and arguments in favor of female education. Her most enduring work, a biography of her husband, included as an appendix to her 24 page memoir, was first published in 1656 as a part of Nature's Pictures. This memoir is regarded as the first major secular autobiography written by a woman.

Books

Alic, Margaret, Hypatia's Heritage: A History of Women in Science from Antiquity through the Nineteenth Century, Beacon Press, 1986.
Battigelli, Anna, Margaret Cavendish and the Exiles of the Mind, University Press of Kentucky, 1998.
Grant, Douglas, Margaret the First: A Biography of Margaret Cavendish, Duchess of Newcastle, 1623-1673, University of Toronto Press, 1957.
Kargon, Robert Hugh, Atomism in England from Hariot to Newton, Clarendon, 1966.
Meyer, Gerald Dennis, The Scientific Lady in England 1650-1760: An Account of her Rise, with emphasis on the Major Roles of the Telescope and Microscope, University of California Press, 1955.
Schiebinger, Londa, The Mind Has No Sex? Women in the Origins of Modern Science, Harvard University Press, 1989.

PIERRE GASSENDI
One of the big influences on Margaret Cavendish's thinking was the Epicurean atomism of Pierre Gassendi.  Here is the link to the Stanford Encylcopedia entry on Gassendi as well as the intro section from it:
http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/gassendi/
Pierre Gassendi (b. 1592, d. 1655) was a French philosopher, scientific chronicler, observer, and experimentalist, scholar of ancient texts and debates, and active participant in contemporary deliberations of the first half of the seventeenth century. His significance in early modern thought has in recent years been rediscovered and explored, towards a better understanding of the dawn of modern empiricism, the mechanical philosophy, and relations of modern philosophy to ancient and medieval discussions. While Gassendi is perhaps best known in history of philosophy for his disputes with Descartes, his relations with other major figures, including Kepler, Galileo, Mersenne, Beeckman, and Hobbes, represented even more important transactions of ideas. And while Gassendi also sought to communicate anew the ideas of Epicurus, the Stoics, and other earlier thinkers, his resulting amalgam of perspectives provides a modern view of his own making, one of the touchstones of philosophy and science in his times: our access to knowledge of the natural world is dependent on the constraints and licenses that follow from our epistemic grasp being limited to information provided by senses. Through this arch-empiricism—tempered by his priestly adherence to key elements of Church doctrine—Gassendi views metaphysics as a realm for speculation grounded in the possibility of empirical confirmation, logic as (by turns) a psychologistic and probabilistic enterprise, knowledge of the external world as built on and forever subject to sensory-based evidence, and ethics in quasi-hedonist, possibly quantifiable terms. Gassendi's philosophy is a constant review of other sources, a thorough consideration of the landscape into which his own empiricism fits and represents an alternative to contrasting claims, past and present. What is sometimes thought of as eclecticism—particularly in the posthumous masterwork, the Syntagma Philosophicum—actually recasts philosophy as a fully-referenced scholarly enterprise, advancing historical styles and rhetorical modes in philosophical research and exposition. In these changes he matches even the magnitude of innovation that marks his atomist matter theory, empiricist perspectives, explorations and defenses of the new physics, objections to the Meditations, and refutations of contemporary Aristotelians and mystical thinkers. It has been argued—perhaps unfairly—that Gassendi's core ideas are better preserved through the medium of writings by Boyle, Locke, Huygens, and Newton. Yet his presentation of an empiricism, atomism, and new cosmology in historical and philosophical context greatly advanced the community of scholarship in his day, and represents what was then a fairly new model of research and exposition—still in philosophical use today.

THE ROYAL SOCIETY
The following link to Jack Lynch's online edition of selections from the Royal Society gives you a sense right away of the rejection of syllogistic reasoning in favor of empirical methodology as well as emphasis on mathematical style in language (a masculine discourse that was opposed to chaotic feminine elements of pleasure):
http://andromeda.rutgers.edu/~jlynch/Texts/sprat.html

Some questions for discussion from Nancy, who is presenting:

 1. The Blazing World has been said to "border on schizophrenia." What is your reaction to that statement?

2. How could a "rhetoric of loss" help us understand this work?

3. What are the components of Cavendish's Utopia?


Bibliographical materials reviewed:


Holmesland, Oddvar, 'Margaret Cavendish's Blazing World:  Natural Art and the Body Politic', Studies in Philology 96: 457-79, 1999.
http://ehis.ebscohost.com.ezproxy.gsu.edu/eds/pdfviewer/pdfviewer?sid=13c5f511-c71c-4f3a-b746-90f987db3228%40sessionmgr111&vid=4&hid=23




In his article entitled “Margaret Cavendish’s The Blazing World: Natural Art and Body Politic” Oddvar Holmesland  takes “a sympathetic view” of Cavendish and her self labeled “ambition.” He seeks to reconcile Cavendish’s contradictory inclinations to portray both an “aristocratic ideology” as well as “a new order where women’s true potential is valued” (Holmesland, 458). Holmesland begins with a review of  criticism aimed at  Cavendish on mostly feminist grounds.  He mentions Lisa T. Sarasohn, who writes that Cavendish “defended the superiority of monarchy and hierarchy, reflecting class rather than gender solidarity” and Susan Wiseman who states that Cavendish “mounted only limited challenges to gender hierarchy.” Holmesland also mentions Janet Todd who suggests that “the Duchess’s immense egoism puffs out any incipient feminist feeling.” Holmesland’s more sympathetic interpretation of Cavendish makes claims that the reader could interpret Cavendish’s wish ‘not only to be Empress, but Authoress of a whole world’... in a ‘poetical’ sense. He centers Cavendish’s achievement  in her creation of an “epistemological space” brought about by  her “artistic vision” (458). Holmesland writes, that Cavendish, “In her artistic vision... explores a more natural Restoration world, expanded and complemented through the individual creative imagination” (459). He finds that The Blazing World offers a dialectic “between an aristocratically conceived natural order and the desire for emulation and singularity’ (459). This notion of singularity is crucial to Holmesland. He finds that there is a transition  “from the ‘ideology of absolute monarchy’ to that of ‘absolute self” (460).
Holmesland states  that critics have noted a dialectic, but “not on the premise of nature” (459). He believes that she seeks to present a “naturalizing” method where “the notion of self becomes relative through references to the motion of nature thought to permeate all individuals, like all matter” (464).  He finds that her “idea of singularity seems closely linked to attaining the privilege of a natural artistic freedom” (460). He states, then, that it would be “reductive” to consider her perspective “solipsistic” (460). From his readings in her Observations,” Holmesland finds  that Cavendish was fascinated with matter and motion - “with self motion being the basic process in a naturally ordered universe“”(463). He believes that she represents “civic humanism” which “treats human affairs, political and economic, in accordance with a presumed law of the universe” (463).  He also finds that her “poetical description” is a means of transcending the limits of empirical observation. He writes that Cavendish uses the imagination, the free mind, as “analogies to nature’s free motion.” (469)  In this way, Cavendish “creates a complex blend of theological, romantic, fantastic, scientifically experimental, and philosophically speculative ode -a kind of “hybridization” (470.) He notes  from her “Observations” that “Art produces Hermaphroditical effects, that is, such are partly Natural, and partly Artificial” (470). Holmesland finds Cavendish expressing that: “poetic freedom allows individuals the opportunity of hybridized self-creation” (475) and that she presents “poetic freedom as a starting point for restoring natural relations among people” (475). Her expression of hermaphrodite space allows the simultaneous consideration of more than one point of view. He believes  that Cavendish creates her own Cabbala where she fashions contradictory elements into a world “of peace and tranquility” (475).
Holmesland writes  that it is “too confining...to sum up The Blazing World as the imaginary voyage of an imperialistic self. Rather, the imperialist vision- the image of the expanded self- also makes a widening artistic and epistemological space” (478). In this epistemological space, Cavendish is then free to explore contradictory ideas concurrently, making The Blazing World a place of freedom  --what one might term an “epistemological community.” Although Holmesland frees Cavendish by placing her artistic aims as beyond the scope of everyday politics and gender issues, positing her strength in the creation of free artistic space, Cavendish, in The Blazing World, still presents readers with a complex work that yields more questions than answers, which may be the point. Cavendish explores and reveals the concerns and anxieties not only of herself as an individual but her society as a whole. Her concept of herself as an individual sits uneasily alongside her concept and support of a national identity. Holmesland gives us some tools to take a look at this hermaphroditic creation.
  (Reviewer, Nancy)

9 comments:

  1. Hey, my undergraduate degree in Philosophy is finally coming in handy! Cavendish, as she appears in the story, attempts to create her own world in the model of several different philosophers, some major, some minor. Rather than trying to explain what *I* remember about these philosophers, here are their (abridged!) entries from the delightfully concise Standford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (complemented by UTSA's more detailed Encyclopedia when useful). I provide this because the Penguin annotations are either not present, misleading, or just too short.

    Thales:

    All that we know about Thales comes from others' reports of him, most famously Aristotle. Many, Aristotle included, believed him to be the first true Greek philosopher.

    SEP--"The reports about Thales show him employing a certain kind of explanation: ultimately the explanation of why things are as they are is grounded in water as the basic stuff of the universe and the changes that it undergoes through its own inherent nature. In this, Thales marks a radical change from all other previous sorts of accounts of the world (both Greek and non-Greek). Like the other Presocratics, Thales sees nature as a complete and self-ordering system, and sees no reason to call on divine intervention from outside the natural world to supplement his account—water itself may be divine, but it is not something that intervenes in the natural world from outside.

    ...

    Thus, on this view, when Thales says that the first principle is water, he should be understood as claiming both that the original state of things was water and that even now (despite appearances), everything is really water in some state or another. The change from the original state to the present one involves changes in the material stuff such that although it may not now appear to be water everywhere (but seems to be airier or earthier than water in its usual state, or its original one), there is no transformation of water into a different kind of stuff (air or earth, for instance). Yet, when Aristotle comes to give what details he can of Thales' view, he suggests only that for Thales, water was the first principle because everything comes from water. Water, then, was perhaps the original state of things for Thales, and water is a necessary condition for everything that is generated naturally, but Aristotle's summary of Thales' view does not imply that Thales claimed that water endures through whatever changes have occurred since the original state, and now just has some new or additional properties. Thales may well have thought that certain characteristics of the original water persisted: in particular its capacity for motion (which must have been innate in order to generate the changes from the original state)"

    That gives you what you need to know about Thales. For a much more detailed account, check out UTSA's entry at http://www.iep.utm.edu/thales/, which addresses everything from controversy surrounding his authorship to his religious views to his cosmology. Sorry, I haven't gotten a chance to talk about the Ancient Greeks in a while! I'll come back and do the other philosophers Cavendish mentions as the week progresses!

    ReplyDelete
  2. Like Thales, none of Pythagoras' works survive. He is most well-known for his mathematical works (such as the Pythagorean Theorem, which he may not have actually invented) and was considered by both Plato and Aristotle to be the first true Greek philosopher. Here's a little bit on his philosophical views:

    "The popular modern image of Pythagoras is that of a master mathematician and scientist. The early evidence shows, however, that, while Pythagoras was famous in his own day and even 150 years later in the time of Plato and Aristotle, it was not mathematics or science upon which his fame rested. Pythagoras was famous (1) as an expert on the fate of the soul after death, who thought that the soul was immortal and went through a series of reincarnations; (2) as an expert on religious ritual; (3) as a wonder-worker who had a thigh of gold and who could be two places at the same time; (4) as the founder of a strict way of life that emphasized dietary restrictions, religious ritual and rigorous self discipline."

    Cavendish clearly uses Pythagoras in his "glorified" (and possibly apocryphal) form, but his actual philosophy is pretty interesting, even if we don't know a whole lot about it. Here's a little on his cosmology:

    " The early evidence suggests, however, that Pythagoras presented a cosmos that was structured according to moral principles and significant numerical relationships and may have been akin to conceptions of the cosmos found in Platonic myths, such as those at the end of the Phaedo and Republic. In such a cosmos, the planets were seen as instruments of divine vengeance (“the hounds of Persephone”), the sun and moon are the isles of the blessed where we may go, if we live a good life, while thunder functioned to frighten the souls being punished in Tartarus. The heavenly bodies also appear to have moved in accordance with the mathematical ratios that govern the concordant musical intervals in order to produce a music of the heavens, which in the later tradition developed into “the harmony of the spheres.” It is doubtful that Pythagoras himself thought in terms of spheres, and the mathematics of the movements of the heavens was not worked out in detail."

    Oh, also, all of that comes from the Stanford Encyclopedia. Also, it's the University of Ten. at Martin who supplies the other encyclopedia I've been quoting, not UTSA. Sorry for the mistake!

    ReplyDelete
  3. I don't think I need add too much about Plato, with whom most of you are probably already familiar. Cavendish references the Platonic notion of Ideas , which I will provide a brief explanation for from Stanford, in case you're unfamiliar with it:

    " The world that appears to our senses is in some way defective and filled with error, but there is a more real and perfect realm, populated by entities (called “forms” or “ideas”) that are eternal, changeless, and in some sense paradigmatic for the structure and character of our world. Among the most important of these abstract objects (as they are now called, because they are not located in space or time) are goodness, beauty, equality, bigness, likeness, unity, being, sameness, difference, change, and changelessness. (These terms—“goodness”, “beauty”, and so on—are often capitalized by those who write about Plato, in order to call attention to their exalted status; similarly for “Forms” and “Ideas.”) The most fundamental distinction in Plato's philosophy is between the many observable objects that appear beautiful (good, just, unified, equal, big) and the one object that is what beauty (goodness, justice, unity) really is, from which those many beautiful (good, just, unified, equal, big) things receive their names and their corresponding characteristics. Nearly every major work of Plato is, in some way, devoted to or dependent on this distinction."

    UTM's page on Plato is lengthy and wonderful and a MUCH better source than his Wikipedia page, which was clearly written by freshmen philosophy students: http://www.iep.utm.edu/plato/

    ReplyDelete
  4. Epicurus was one of the major post-Aristotlean philosophers and a few of his works survive. We know most of what we know about him from the school of Epicureanism which sprang out of his teachings and which persisted for quite a while after his death. Though both Stanford and UTM do a good job summarizing his philosophy, you really only need to know his atomist principles (Cavendish herself having written much atomistic work) to know how Cavendish is using him. As such, I will provide the briefest of summaries of the school of Epicureanism, provided by the Oxford English Dictionary: "The distinctive doctrines of Epicurus were, 1. That the highest good is pleasure, which he identified with the practice of virtue. 2. That the gods do not concern themselves at all with men's affairs. 3. That the external world resulted from a fortuitous concourse of atoms."

    The first of these points is where we derive the word "epicurean," which in older texts means something like "hedonistic" and more current ones means something like "connoisseur." However, it is the latter point which Cavendish is most interested in. Here is Stanford's explication of Epicurus' atomism:

    "Epicurus held that the elementary constituents of nature are undifferentiated matter, in the form of discrete, solid and indivisible particles (“atoms”) below the threshold of perception, plus empty space. In its broad outline, Epicurus inherited this scheme from the earlier atomists, above all Democritus.

    ...

    First, he distinguished between the atom, which by its nature cannot be broken apart, and the minimum conceivable expanse of matter: atoms have such minima as parts, but are not minima themselves — there can be no free-standing entity one minimum expanse in size. This resolves the problem of atomic edges, and also that of how atoms can come in different shapes and sizes (though never large enough to be seen): to have the hooks and crevices needed to form compounds, they can scarcely be theoretically partless. Second, Epicurus agreed that time too is discontinuous, as is motion: Simplicius (p. 934.23–30 Diels; translation in Konstan 1989) quotes him as affirming that it is untrue to say that an atom is moving over a minimum interval, but only that it has moved. What is more, as Aristotle had argued must be the case, atoms all move at the same velocity (the principle of isotakheia). This last claim entailed difficulties of its own, such as how atoms ever overtake each other, if they are moving in the same direction. (Lucretius invoked the idea of a random swerve to solve this one; see below.) But it also provided a solution to another problem, that of entropy: for since atoms can never slow down, the universe can never come to a halt (in modern terms, there is no loss of energy). As for gravity, Epicurus may have had a solution to this too, and in a novel form. If an atom just on its own cannot slow down or alter its direction of motion, then an atom that is rising or moving in an oblique direction cannot at some point begin to tilt or fall, unless something blocks its progress and forces it to do so. If, however, after a collision atoms tended to emerge in a statistically favored direction — that is, if the motions of all atoms after collisions did not cancel each other out but on average produced a vector, however small, in a given direction, then that direction would by definition be down. The absence of a global orientation in the universe was thus immaterial."

    There's more, but you can see from this how, in a universe with no global orientation and atoms of infinite indivisibility, the fictional Cavendish could be in a "mist."

    ReplyDelete
  5. Aristotle is one of the most important philosophers in the Western philosophy's history and you're probably already familiar with him, so I'll just clarify a bit the section of his philosophy that Cavendish references. The idea that "nothing can come from nothing" is from Aristotle's response to Parmenides in his "Physics." Here is a good summation of that passage from Washington University: "Aristotle gives his response to Parmenides in chapter 8. He begins (191a28-29) by summarizing the Parmenidean argument against coming to be that we mentioned above:

    What is cannot come to be (since it already is), while nothing can come to be from what is not.
    The idea of this argument seems to be this: in a case of coming to be, the resulting object is clearly a being, something that is. From what initial object does it come to be? Parmenides offers us only two choices: either what is or what is not. But if the initial object is what is, and the resultant object is also what is, we don’t really have a case of coming to be-there is no change. And if the initial object is what is not, we have another kind of impossibility, for nothing can come to be from what is not (ex nihilo nihil fit).

    Aristotle’s response is to reject the Parmenidean dilemma “that something comes to be from what is or from what is not” (191a30). He does so, characteristically, by drawing a distinction where his opponents did not. At 191b4 he says:

    … we speak in two ways when we say that something is or comes to be something from what is …
    Is the initial object a being or a not-being, Parmenides asks? Aristotle’s answer is: in a way it’s a being, and in a way it’s a not-being. And in a way, it’s not a being, and in a way it’s not a not-being.

    In effect, the trouble with the Parmenidean argument is that it treats the initial and resultant objects as if they were simples: not being and being. But, as Aristotle has shown, both are compounds. The initial object, for example, might be an unmusical man. And this is both in one way a being and in another way a not being: the initial object is something that is (for it is a man) and something that is not (for it is not musical).

    As for Parmenides’ claim that nothing can come to be from what is not, Aristotle agrees that, on one reading, this is perfectly correct (191b14):

    We agree with them in saying that nothing comes to be without qualification from what is not …
    That is, the musician does not come into existence out of thin air, out of sheer nothingness. (We should probably take “without qualification” here to modify “what is not” rather than “comes to be”—“comes to be from what is unqualifiedly not” or “comes to be from what is simply a not-being.”) But this leaves room, Aristotle says, for the musician to come to be from what in a way is not (191b15).

    … but we say that things come to be in a way—for instance, coincidentally—from what is not. For something comes to be from the privation, which in itself is not and does not belong to the thing [when it has come to be].

    (Similarly, we should take “in a way” to modify “what is not” rather than “comes to be.”) In other words, since the musician comes to be from the compound unmusical man, what he comes to be from is in one way a not-being, since he comes to be from a privation-the unmusical. But in a way, what he comes to be from is a being, as well, for the initial object is something that exists, a man. Parmenides, in other words, offers us a false dilemma: that the initial object is either being or not being. But since the initial object is a compound, in a way it is both."

    ReplyDelete
  6. Rene Descartes is traditionally only known for his work in rational philosophy, but Cavendish highlights his work in modern physics, for which he is becoming increasingly renowned. Here's a summary of his "globules, from Stanford: "Descartes' vortex theory of planetary motion proved initially to be one of the most influential aspects of Cartesian physics, at least until roughly the mid-eighteenth century. A vortex, for Descartes, is a large circling band of material particles. In essence, Descartes' vortex theory attempts to explain celestial phenomena, especially the orbits of the planets or the motions of comets, by situating them (usually at rest) in these large circling bands. The entire Cartesian plenum, consequently, is comprised of a network or series of separate, interlocking vortices. In our solar system, for example, the matter within the vortex has formed itself into a set of stratified bands, each lodging a planet, that circle the sun at varying speeds. The minute material particles that form the vortex bands consist of either the atom-sized, globules (secondary matter) or the “indefinitely” small debris (primary matter) left over from the impact and fracture of the larger elements; tertiary matter, in contrast, comprises the large, macroscopic material element (Pr III 48–54). This three-part division of matter, along with the three laws of nature, are responsible for all cosmological phenomena in Descartes' system, including gravity. As described in Pr III 140, a planet or comet comes to rest in a vortex band when its radially-directed, outward tendency to flee the center of rotation (i.e., centrifugal force; see Section 6) is balanced by an equal tendency in the minute elements that comprise the vortex ring. If the planet has either a greater or lesser centrifugal tendency than the small elements in a particular vortex, then it will, respectively, either ascend to the next highest vortex (and possibly reach equilibrium with the particles in that band) or be pushed down to the next lowest vortex—and this latter scenario ultimately supplies Descartes' explanation of the phenomenon of gravity, or “heaviness”. More specifically, Descartes holds that the minute particles that surround the earth account for terrestrial gravity in this same manner (Pr IV 21–27). As for the creation of the vortex system, Descartes reasons that the conserved quantity of motion imparted to the plenum eventually resulted in the present vortex configuration (Pr III 46). God first partitioned the plenum into equal-sized portions, and then placed these bodies into various circular motions that, ultimately, formed the three elements of matter and the vortex systems."

    ReplyDelete
  7. Thomas Hobbes, a contemporary and acquaintance of Cavendish, is well-known for his somewhat misanthropic philosophy. I believe Cavendish is responding to the attitude of his work and not anything in his work proper, but here is UTM's summary of his moral/political philosophy (to which Cavendish alludes) for those interested: http://www.iep.utm.edu/hobmoral/

    ReplyDelete
  8. Also, Stanford has an EXCELLENT section on Cavendish, here: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/margaret-cavendish/.

    If you don't want to read it all, here are some of the good parts:

    "Margaret Lucas Cavendish was a philosopher, poet, scientist, fiction-writer, and playwright who lived in the seventeenth century. Her work is important for a number of reasons. One is that it lays out an early and very compelling version of the naturalism that is found in current-day philosophy and science.

    ...

    The central tenet of Cavendish's philosophy is that everything in the universe—including human beings and their minds—is completely material. Her commitment to this tenet is reflected throughout her corpus:

    Nature is material, or corporeal, and so are all her Creatures, and whatsoever is not material is no part of Nature, neither doth it belong any ways to Nature….[2]
    According to Cavendish, none of the achievements of bodies are to be traced to immaterial agents such as God, immaterial finite minds, or substantial forms, because bodies have the resources to bring about everything that they do on their own. Bodies are ubiquitous, because there is no vacuum, as extensions of space cannot be extensions of nothing but must be extensions of matter.[3] Every body is infinitely divisible (Cavendish 1668a, 125, 263; Cavendish 1668b, 239), and all of the bodies in nature, at every level of division, are intelligent and perceptive (Cavendish 1668a, 16, 156; Cavendish 1668b, 7). As we will see, one of Cavendish's motivations for accepting the latter view is that it makes sense of the order that we encounter in the natural world.

    ...

    Cavendish is working within a philosophical tradition in which the doctrine that matter is self-moving and intelligent is almost completely unintelligible. To those of her opponents who allow that the doctrine can be entertained, it is unlikely at best, and if true it is a terrible disappointment."

    There's SO much more, but her ideas that everything is material and matter can think are what really separates her as a philosopher!

    ReplyDelete